"A Secular Age": Introduction
Taylor’s ‘Introduction’ sets out the questions his big book hopes to answer. He claims we live now in a ‘secular age’ whereas we used to live in a ‘religious age’—impossible to disagree about this I think—and wants to know how this change came about. The earlier age was one in which ‘the political organisation’ was ‘connected to, based on, guaranteed by some faith in, or adherence to God, or some notion of ultimate reality’ where ‘the modern Western state is free from this connection.’ He’s intrigued that it used to be impossible to disbelieve in God, in the sense that social sanction compelled the public profession of belief, whereas now it’s perfectly fine to declare oneself an atheist.
Earlier than that, before the ‘official’ combination of
society and religion of (say) the European Middle Ages, Taylor, in passing,
posits archaic societies in which the distinctions between religion, politics,
economics, society and so on simply did not apply: ‘in these earlier societies,
religion was “everywhere”, was interwoven with everything else, and in no sense
constituted a separate “sphere” of its own’. (p.2)
Now obviously A Secular Age is vast, full of detail, committed
throughout to try and apprehend the ‘social imaginaries’ it is exploring with
as much nuance as possible; and I’d say (from having dipped into the book
before, and from reading accounts of it) that for Taylor this shift from a
religious to a secular age must account for the fact that the God people used to
have to believe in is still there in some sense—as a man of faith
himself, he’s obviously not going to be happy with an argument that boils down
to ‘all those early men and women were suckers, and now we know better’. And
it’s interesting to me that he also repudiates what he calls ‘subtraction
narratives’, the Wordsworth’s immortality ode myth of human development, that
we used to have access to the authentic numinous and now we’ve somehow,
inexplicably lost it—shades of the prison house cast, perhaps, by materialism,
capitalism, science, selfishness or sin.
Nonetheless I think it’s worth at least sketching out the
naive view that Taylor considers beneath his notice: the vulgar narrative that
puts the emphasis not on strategies of human flourishing but on strategies of
human comprehension. After all, we know a lot more about a lot more
things nowadays than did archaic man, who lacked any understanding of Newton’s
laws, germ theory etc. Mightn’t this fact, on its own, cut the gordian knot of
Taylor’s big question?
So instead of a model of archaic men and women inhabiting a world,
as Taylor proposes, in which religion was everywhere interwoven with everything
else, I’m going to float a model in which religion develops, in its earliest
form, as a separate magisterium from most of the business of living. Because
I think this throws a different light on his way of framing his questions.
The argument would go like this. Start by hypothesising that
animals don’t have ‘religion’ in the sense that Charles Taylor does. This means
that, at some point on our evolutionary path, we humans began to develop it. Then:
speculate that this happened in order to provide an explanation for the
inexplicable, and that as our consciousnesses and mental capacity grew over
the long-timescales upon which evolution works, ‘the inexplicable’—and its
already attendant modus explicatus, religion—came to colonise more and
more of our lived experience, until eventually we reached a time when it seemed
common-sense to people that religion stood as the explanation for everything.
So: there are many aspects of our lives that don’t present
to us as mysterious—or more precisely if these aspects sometimes present
to some of us today (philosophers, say) as mysterious, that’s only
because habits of thought have developed in which we deliberately set out
to challenge everything we assume, and refuse to take anything on trust. But
most people are not Wittgenstein, and this non-Wittgensteinness was surely truer
of early man than it is true of modern man. So I repeat myself: there are many
aspects of our lives that don’t present to us as mysterious. You are hungry. You
eat, and you stop being hungry. That, for early man, is not a mystery. It may
be a practical challenge (how to find food) but it is not a puzzle that
food stops us feeling hungry. That’s just what food does, it’s just the way
things are.
I’d suggest a piece of evidence that this has been so for
much of human existence is to be found in the observation that no culture has
developed a god of hunger. Cultures have certainly developed gods of food—the
Greek Demeter, say; or the Christian shepherd-and-fisherman god Jesus—but not
because food is a mystery as such, but rather because food supply is
uncertain, and this uncertainty is a worry and (therefore) a puzzle. The puzzle
begins in the practical: what can we do to ensure that our food supply
continues, so we don’t starve? (Perhaps we can, in effect, speak to the manager,
identify who’s in charge and propitiate him/her). Once this step is taken, it
expands backward (as it were) into the conceptual. That’s my speculation, at
any rate.
In other words, the function of the gods, for early man, was
not a Taylorian business of maximising fulfilment
via an external focus, so much as it was a way of explaining the otherwise unexplainable.
Lightning strikes are alarming and inexplicable; ‘Zeus’ is an explanation that
carries with it the twin practical advantages of reducing those anxieties that
attend ignorance and of providing us with a (spurious of course, but perhaps that
matters less than one might think) mode of addressing the danger—for by
propitiating Zeus we can hope to avoid being struck by lightning.
Beast-life, in this model, would be godless: the dynamic of
appetite and the satisfaction of appetite, a focus of avoiding danger and locating
prey and so on. Gods enter upon the scene when things need—need in an
evolutionary sense: the sense in which finding answers starts to provide an
evolutionary advantage—to be explained. There is no god of fucking, because
fucking—as fucking—is an animal appetite and an animal satisfaction, one
we humans share with pigeons and horses and so on. But there are gods of
fertility (for us, not for the pigeons) because once humans become aware of the
relationship between fucking and babies, and more importantly once they become
anxious at the prospect of not producing babies, or desirous of
maximising the production of babies, or of ensuring their distinct paternity, a
god becomes both explanation for this strange causal propinquity and site of
propitiation for its uncertainties. Once gods have become common in our
understanding of the universe, once humans are used to seeing the world as full
of them, then a god of fucking (call her Aphrodite) becomes retrofitted
back into the pantheon. But there’s little doubt that fertility fetishes, and
potency/fertility gods and goddesses, predate these later retcons. [1]
Similarly: there is no god of anger as such, since anger is
an animal passion. But once anger becomes socialised and codified into war—with
all its thrills, uncertainties and anxieties—well then we get war
gods. The thesis in other words is that the grit around which these pearlescent
gods grow, in the oyster shells of human society, is an substantive uncertainty,
and the function they serve is twofold: one, explanation in terms both of
how and why (‘what is that alarming lightning strike?’ ‘It is God throwing
thunderbolts.’ ‘But why does God do so?’ ‘He is punishing those who stand against him!’) and two,
an opportunity of controlling, or averting, the uncertainty (‘to avoid
being struck by lightning, we must propitiate God.’)
This theory is predicated on humankind being defined as
humankind insofar as they have evolved a beyond-beast will-to-understanding, a
curiosity, an unhappiness about the unexplained, the uncertain, and a satisfaction
in finding both how and why explanations for things. It depends, indeed, upon
seeing humans as centrally invested in making sense of things, in a way
not true of other animals. I’m aware this sounds like a scientist’s
idealisation of humankind (though I am not a scientist), but it's surely logical, in terms of our survival, to say that we have collectively evolved both the desire and some of
the capacity to anticipate risk, danger etc. But I’m aware that not everybody
would concur with this as a ‘definition’ of what it means to be human, or what
separates us from the animals.
By this account, then, religion is separate from the rest of
the business of existing, in the first instance: ‘how do we turn these grains
of wheat into bread?’ is an uncertainty that is not addressed by saying: ‘we
must propitiate the gods’, but rather by practical strategies of threshing,
winnowing etc. On the other hand, ‘how do we ensure rain falls on our
wheatfields so the crops don’t die?’ is an uncertainty that, for most of human
history, has provoked in us a supernatural response. Or so I’d guess.
I wonder if these two things, explanation and propitiation,
could be proposed as alternatives to the argument Taylor develops. So, A
Secular Age is very interested in the question of humankind’s (innate,
Taylor seems to suggest) orientation toward something ‘beyond human flourishing’,
beyond the simple animal-selfish gratifications and towards Buddhist
annihilation of self and Christian and Muslim individual and collective
self-sacrifice. But I’d suggest that these things grew, perhaps, out of the
propitiation aspect of the earliest forms of gods makes sense to me, since
propitiation had to incur a cost to be worthwhile, and inflation is a property
that touches human emotional and psychological lives just as it does economics.
Now, my explanation may be hooey.[2] But if there’s anything in it, it provides one big (simple, or if you prefer over-simplistic) answer to Taylor’s big question: why did we move from a religious to a secular society? Because secular discourses of science proved better at explaining things than the earlier religious discourses did, at least on the level of ‘how’. I honestly don’t think that’s a controversial thing to claim. Physics is manifestly better at explaining lightning strikes than ancient Greek theology, and can give us better advice on how to avoid being hit by them too. People who still cleave to religious worldviews would, perhaps, point to the paucity of convincing ‘why’ explanations in science, but in evolutionary terms ‘how’ explanations are likely to be of more immediate, hands-on use than ‘why’ ones.
But if this explanation has anything in it, it entails a
number of problems. For instance, if I’m right that one of the social and
personal ‘functions’ of gods was to offer explanations for things, to enhance
our sense (even if spuriously) that we understood how the larger world worked,
then it seems strange to me that the polarity of ‘God’ as a concept has flipped
about so completely, such that nowadays it is a benchmark of faith that God is radically
non-understandable, that He is beyond our capacity to reason, prove, or
reduce to logic, that He is a profound mystery and so on. That (the flip-about,
I mean) seems a little … odd, I suppose. But perhaps this is less odd than I’m
suggesting. Empirically it is the case that people otherwise not especially religious turn to ‘God’ when the
regular rhythms of their mundane life are disrupted, for instance by sufferings or bereavements that doesn’t make sense—that are inexplicable—in existential
terms. In these circumstances ‘God’ fills the same function it may have done
for early man.
Again, I’m aware that this approach, by starting to talk
about God as a function, premises discussion on a notion of God conceived instrumentally,
which will not convince people of faith for whom God is the ground of
existence as such, not a mere advantageous addition to individual or collective
existences. Nonetheless I think it connects—perhaps I only think it
connects—with another thing Taylor says in his introduction.
So he concedes that his term ‘secular’ is a problem (‘I have
been struggling with the sense of “secular” and “secularity”, 14), and in this
introduction is content to leave it gestured-towards, to be fleshed-out as he
goes on, rather that trying to pin things down more precisely (or
faux-precisely). That’s fine. But he does go some way towards definition, by breaking
the term down into ‘three modes’. Those three are: [1] replacing faith with
‘reason’, especially a kind of reification of reason as the only way to live,
to order society etc (‘the Kantian form is the most upfront about this: we have
the power as rational agency to make the laws by which we live—this is
something so greatly superior to the force of mere nature in us, in the form of
desire, that when we contemplate it without distortion we cannot but feel
reverence’, p.8). Then [2] ‘Nature’—I think Taylor is thinking of Romanticism
here: ‘Reason’ is desiccated and inwards, Nature seen as a value that transcends
the individual, an outward-focused source of virtue (‘Reason by itself is
narrow, blind to the demands of fullness’; the critique of ‘Reason’ locates the
sources of its power not in anything transcendent but ‘in Nature, or in our own
inner depths, or in both’ p.9). Taylor’s [3] is, I suppose, ‘postmodernism’,
that ‘scoffs at the claims of self-sufficient reason’ but ‘offer[s] no outside
source for the reception of power’ (p.10). All three, by Taylor’s reading, tend
inward, where religious flourishing (he says) has an outward focus. The intro
ends with him restating this distinction in terms of a transcendence/ immanence
distinction.
‘We have moved from a world in
which the place of fullness was understood as unproblematically outside or “beyond”
human life, to a conflicted age in which this construal is challenged by others
which place it (in a wide range of different ways) “within” human life.’ [15]
… where ‘fullness’, here (slightly evasively, maybe?) is
defined by Taylor as his ‘shorthand term here for the condition we aspire to,’
but for which ‘there is no perfect terminological solution’ in terms of
definition, such that with ‘reservations’ Taylor is prepared to ‘let the word
stand.’ The danger is that this conflates two modes of positive existential
experience: the epiphanic spot-of-time moment Taylor quotes (via Griffith) in
p.5, and a blander positive mode of day-to-day existence, fulfilled and
content—chronos as opposed to the other kind of ‘fullness’s’ kairos,
to use Frank Kermode’s terms. ‘Somewhere, in some activity, or condition, lies
a fullness, a richness; that is, in that place (activity or condition), life is
fuller, richer, deeper, more worthwhile, more admirable, more what it should
be.’ [p.5]
Anyway I think his three-fold anatomy of ‘secularism’,
‘Reason’ / ‘Nature’ / ‘Postmodernism’, is insufficient, really. Maybe Taylor expands
upon it as his book continues, but it seems to me on its face to omit what are,
actually, the major iterations of secular existence nowadays, none of which are really predicated upon these three—kinds of contemporary secular existence that (we
might think, aping earlier religious communal life) cultivate this kind of
fullness precisely by fixing on an outwardness rather than an inwardness. I’m
talking about those people nowadays who find their fullness through belonging
to a group of like-minded people, focused on politics (say) or on one of the
various fandoms that exist (eg SF), on music, or sports—watching or playing.
This is most people, I think, and it is neither merely rational, nor Romantic
Nature-ism—nor, although given our historical moment, there’s a lot of pomo
ironic posturing and code-switched etc, is it actually ironic. People who are
passionate about music, going to gigs and festivals, listening to it, reading
about it etc, are fixing a value on something outside themselves, something
that enables communitarian connection and one-ness (Nietzsche etc), not as
rational actors but quasi-religious but secular fans.
Anyway, I think it’s worth laying all this out, like this,
if only because the topics A Secular Age addresses are (important) things
to which we all come with priors, biases, of one kind or another. Taylor (so
far as I can tell) isn’t interested in paleological religion, or
pre-history—his historical scope is, really, medieval-to-modern, with
occasional looks-back to classical Rome. Plenty to be getting on with, just on
that timescale, no question. And obviously I shouldn’t second-guess him, but I
suspect that one of his priors is—the long history of human religion is
one where we go from ‘earlier societies [in which] religious was “everywhere”,
was interwoven with everything else, and in no sense constituted a separate
“sphere” of its own’, to early modernity when religion was not separate from
society and politics but had become in some sense reified or alienated from
some aspects of day-to-day life, to our modern secular separated-out world. It
makes sense that Taylor would think this, because (I presume) he considers
religion ‘true’, and regards belief in God as a justified belief; and the
large-scale narrative of human existence as been a path from existence being
suffused in God to a kind of complicated new secularised orientation makes
sense in that frame. But these are not my priors. That fact alone may get in
the way of me being able to do proper justice to Taylor’s ideas, I know.
[1] I’m no expert (of course) but so far as I can see historians of the prehistoric roots of religion argue something along these lines: religious praxis, so far as we can tell, begins with the use of small fetish objects and representational images (like cave paintings). These are mostly of [a] curvaceous female forms and [b] animals—the former as a focus for devotional activity designed to ensure fertility, and the latter to increase the chances of success in the hunt. Penates, or ‘household gods’—also fetish objects—developed later as a focus for devotional activity to ensure the safety and sanctity of the home. These latter were a very long-lived religious cultus: Vergil is still invoking them at around the time of Christ’s birth. (Ancestor worship also has a place here, although I'm not sure anyone quite knows where exactly). From here, gods were later imagined as personified externalities, often (there’s a continuity here I suppose) in the form of a superior kind of animal being—dog-, stag- or lion-headed figures let’s say. Purely human-like gods were a later development. The more rarefied notion of ‘One God’, initially a strange heresy of the Jews, came very much later.
[2] I
haven’t encountered this thesis precisely argued in any of the histories of
religion I have read, although I haven’t read very many—there’s such a
lot of this material, I’ve only glanced at some of it, and may be spouting
nonsense. Also, looking even briefly into all this stuff makes me realise the
extent to which it's all educated guesswork and speculation anyway, because
there’s almost no hard evidence. So far as I can see the most influential
anthropological theory of how religions arose nowadays is the one advanced in Stewart
Elliott’s Faces in the Clouds: A New Theory of Religion (Oxford
University Press 1995) and Justin Barrett’s ‘Exploring the Natural Foundations
of Religion’ Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4:1 (2000): 29–34. Barrett posits
not a will-to-curiosity (as I’m doing here), but rather what he calls a ‘hyperactive
agency detection device,’ or HADD, as an explanation for the origins of
religious beliefs. ‘The HADD is a cognitive module which evolved to scan the
environment for signs of agency, such as twigs breaking in nearby woods, in
order to alert an individual to opportunity or danger. Because fellow agents
are key sources of both danger and of aid, they are profoundly relevant for
fitness, and, as such, our brains evolved to be hypersensitive to cues of
agency. As a result, the default calibration of the human mind produces more
false positive alarms than false negatives. In other words, it is better to
wrongly impute, say, an imaginary tiger in the nearby bushes than to fail to
identify a real one. Equipped with the HADD, the reasoning goes, human minds
can scarcely avoid coming up with supernatural agent beliefs, since they are
incessantly scaring up thoughts of invisible agents’ [Connor Wood and John H.
Shaver ‘Religion, Evolution, and the Basis of Institutions: The Institutional
Cognition Model of Religion’ Evolutionary Studies in Imaginative Culture,
2:2 (2018), 3]. Wood and Shaver, there, note the wide influence this ‘HADD’
model has exerted on subsequent theorising about the origins of religion: for
instance in Scott Atran, In Gods We Trust: The Evolutionary Landscape of
Religion (2002) and Robert N McCauley, Why Religion Is Natural and
Science Is Not (2013).
Adam, two thoughts:
ReplyDelete1) I wonder if Taylor’s argument is agnostic with regard to explanations for religion? I’m not sure it depends on any particular one.
2) A few weeks ago I might have been more sympathetic to your account of the origins of religion, but as it happens I have been reading, really seriously for the first time, Durkheim’s Elementary Forms of the Religious Life, and Durkheim doesn’t think that religion has anything to do with explaining phenomena. He thinks it is always and everywhere a means of forming and sustaining “moral community.”
1) I agree his argument doesn't depend on any particular theory of the *origins* of religion, but I'd still suggest it makes a difference to his argument what he thinks religion (as it were) *does* for us. The "human flourishing by focusing on a higher reality outside ourselves" part is important, not least because it informs eg porosity/bufferedness (doesn't it?) Where if religion's role is to provide first practical but nowadays more existential *explanations* of things, porosity/bufferedness becomes less salient (in other words I'm floating the thesis that religion used to be about answering a number of "how?" uncertainties but is now largely about "why?" uncertainties, from "why are we here? what's the point of life?" on down to "why did cancer take my wife?" or "why should I help my neighbour" and so on). But I have to admit that I'm not, even in myself, sure of this. For instance it strikes me that Elliot and Barrett's "hyperactive agency detection device" theory of religion's beginnings is much more compatible with Taylor's argument that we've moved from porous sensibilities to buffered ones --- for early humans lived in a world where being open to these signs of agented activity was vital to survival, and so had to be "porous" to them; but now we've extruded a world around us designed, by and large, to keep us safe (at least from tigers and famine and so on), and so we can afford to buffer ourselves.
Delete2) Here you outflank me, sir: I've read about Durkheim, but never actually read Durkheim. I shall have to, clearly!
> 2) A few weeks ago I might have been more sympathetic to your account of the origins of religion, but [...] Durkheim doesn’t think that religion has anything to do with explaining phenomena. He thinks it is always and everywhere a means of forming and sustaining “moral community.”
DeleteCame here to say this (religion like art provides social-action-at-a-distance, selected evolutionarily for its signification/socialization effects while generating knock-on *explanatory* effects), though not to mention Durkheim, having forgotten every word of his that I'd read within five minutes of the class discussions for which they were assigned.
> 2) A few weeks ago I might have been more sympathetic to your account of the origins of religion, but [...] Durkheim doesn’t think that religion has anything to do with explaining phenomena. He thinks it is always and everywhere a means of forming and sustaining “moral community.”
DeleteCame here to say this (religion like art provides social-action-at-a-distance, selected evolutionarily for its signification/socialization effects while generating knock-on *explanatory* effects), though not to mention Durkheim, having forgotten every word of his that I'd read within five minutes of the class discussions for which they were assigned.
> 2) A few weeks ago I might have been more sympathetic to your account of the origins of religion, but [...] Durkheim doesn’t think that religion has anything to do with explaining phenomena. He thinks it is always and everywhere a means of forming and sustaining “moral community.”
DeleteCame here to say this (religion like art provides social-action-at-a-distance, selected evolutionarily for its signification/socialization effects while generating knock-on *explanatory* effects), though not to mention Durkheim, having forgotten every word of his that I'd read within five minutes of the class discussions for which they were assigned.
As Tennyson might have said, surely better to have read Durkheim and forgotten it than never to have read Durkheim at all.
DeleteI still think my "why has no human culture worshipped a god of hunger?" point a good one. But I suppose I would say that, wouldn't I.
Your first point reminds me of something I have said to my students: that the buffered self may to some extent be the product less of purely intellectual changes than of the Industrial Revolution. Ditto the sublime as something desirable to encounter. When Lewis and Clark's men were faced with crossing the Bitterroot Range in Montana, one of them wrote in his journal that he was looking at "the most terrible mountains." Enjoyment of that landscape's sublimity may have had to wait for waterproof books, down parkas, and automobiles that can take us back to a nice hotel after our temporarily porous encounter with sublimity.
ReplyDeleteDurkheim is really getting to me. A sociologist friend calls Formes Elementaires de la Vie Religieuse “that amazing and infuriating book” — and also tells me that sociologists initialize it as FEVER. It produces one in me. Not to get too far from Taylor, but Durkheim’s argument that religion is a means of identifying and coalescing the community in symbolic form really helps to explain the ways that religious thought and practice can outlive the structures we call “religion.” I wish I had read this book before writing some of my recent essays.
I meant waterproof BOOTS, though waterproof books are helpful also.
Delete