Modern Social Imaginaries
Part 1 of A Secular Age is called ‘The Work of Reform’ and
is disposed into five chapters: ‘The Bulwarks of Belief’; ‘The Rise of the
Disciplinary Society’; ‘The Great Disembedding’; ‘Modern Social Imaginaries’
and ‘The Spectre of Idealism’. What is being laboriously reformed in Part 1? Society and the belief-systems that undergird it.
Taylor’s narrative concerns the circumstances
underpinning the shift from a basically religious to a basically secular
society, but (to quote Michael Morgan) this is ‘not a history of doctrines or
theories’ but rather ‘a history of the background conditions that made various
doctrinal and practical ways of life possible’ what Taylor calls the ‘social
imaginaries’ of lived experience: sensibilities, frameworks of subjectivity and
intersubjectivity, worldviews, ‘the self-understandings of our social existence’.
There are lots of ideas in this (book-length!) chunk of prose, but two are of particular importance, and, I'd say, influence. One is the distinction Taylor makes between ‘porous’ selves and ‘buffered’ selves—I’ll have more to say about this later. The other is addressed in the fourth chapter here: the ‘social imaginary’.
Now, this, as a concept, looks rather familiar, I'd say: something like Bourdieu’s ‘habitus’, or perhaps an Althusser-ish spin on ideology. But Taylor is adamant he’s trying to articulate something else, that ‘what I am trying to get at with this term is something much broader and deeper than the intellectual schemes people may entertain when they think about social reality in a disengaged mode’ (p.171). So what is it? Well: it is ‘complex’. It ‘incorporates a sense of the normal expectations that we have of each other’:
the kind or common understanding
which enables us to carry out the collective practices which make up our social
life. This incorporates some sense of how we all fit together in carrying out
the common practice. This understanding is both factual and ‘normative’; that
is, we have a sense of how things usually go. but this is interwoven with an
idea of how they ought to go, of what mis-steps would invalidate the practice.
(p.172)
Taylor identifies ‘three important forms of social
self-understanding’ as particularly important to his larger argument: ‘(1) the
“economy”, (2) the public sphere, and (3) ‘the practices and outlooks of
democratic self-rule’ (p.176).
I’m not convinced this is that different, actually,
from (say) Bordieu’s Habitus, or Althusser’s ideological interpellation. But I
may be doing Taylor an injustice. He sees this social imaginary as rooted in
what he called the ‘modern moral order’, which he says ‘played a central role
in the development of modern Western
society’ (p.159). He derives this from Grotius, via Locke, which made me wonder
how his argument might have been different if he’d derived it instead from Richard
Hooker’s prior Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity—much more than just a work
of theology, or Anglican apologetics; and very influential, it establishes, or
tries to, a grounded theory of politics, law and social community. Factoring in
Hooker would make it harder for Taylor to insist that the new moral order was
all Lockean, all ‘Industrious and Rational’ (p.167), which would diminish the force of his larger argument.
At any rate, that’s not the route Taylor wants to go down.
The Gospel generates the idea of
a community of saints, inspired by love for God, for each other, and for
humankind, whose members were devoid of rivalry, mutual resentment, love of
gain, ambition to rule and the like. (p.161)
I think Taylor offers this as a kind of prototype of his moral order (‘something to strive for, realized by some [though] only a minority will really succeed’), but I’m not sure it’s … true, though? He’s talking about the disciples (isn’t he?), whose number included Judas, thrice-denier Peter, doubting Thomas and so on. I mean, one of the most remarkable things about the Gospel is its (novelistic, as Kermode argues) portrayal of a band of enthusiastic but flawed and rough-edged men. Isn’t it?
Once we are well installed in the
modern social imaginary, it seems the only possible one. After all, are we not
all individuals? Do we not associate in society for our mutual benefit? How
else to measure social life? (p.168)
This is a VERY important point!
ReplyDelete